Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: https://hdl.handle.net/1959.11/55246
Full metadata record
DC FieldValueLanguage
dc.contributor.authorGhosh, Ericen
dc.date.accessioned2023-07-20T03:16:36Z-
dc.date.available2023-07-20T03:16:36Z-
dc.date.issued2000-01-
dc.identifier.citationAustralasian Journal of Legal Philosophy, 25(2), p. 273-285en
dc.identifier.issn1440-4982en
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/1959.11/55246-
dc.description.abstract<p>One of the interesting issues raised by Philip Pettit's paper and book is the significance of his distinction between liberal and republican liberty. To articulate a few of the many ways in which this issue could be considered, one could, adopting a historical approach, compare the republican and liberal traditions in order to test Pettit's account of the two conceptions of liberty' and the shift from republican to liberal liberty. The usefulness of the two conceptions in capturing imponant aspects of the traditions could also be examined. Alternatively, adopting an analytical approach, we could accept Pettit's interpretation of republican and liberal liberty and the role of these values within the normative frameworks of republicanism and liberalism, and then question whether republicanism is superior. Pettit argues that liberal liberty is, in one imponant respect, narrower than republican liberty. While he recognises that left-of-centre liberals can overcome this narrowness by consulting a range of values, he claims that republicanism has the advantage of simplicity: in deciding issues, it is sufficient to consult the single value of republican liberty. However, it can be argued that the complexity of the 1ibera1 approach is not problematic if consulting republican liberty alone leads us to ignore imponant values or if it leads to a similar level of complexity, in terms of assessing and weighing many different considerations. Both difficulties appear in Pettit's application of republican liberty to the criminal justice system, and one could question whether they also affect Pettit's treatment of constitutional matters.</p>en
dc.languageenen
dc.publisherAustralasian Society of Legal Philosophyen
dc.relation.ispartofAustralasian Journal of Legal Philosophyen
dc.titleRepublican Liberty and Constitutional Constraintsen
dc.typeJournal Articleen
local.contributor.firstnameEricen
local.profile.schoolSchool of Lawen
local.profile.emaileghosh@une.edu.auen
local.output.categoryC1en
local.record.placeauen
local.record.institutionUniversity of New Englanden
local.publisher.placeAustraliaen
local.format.startpage273en
local.format.endpage285en
local.peerreviewedYesen
local.identifier.volume25en
local.identifier.issue2en
local.contributor.lastnameGhoshen
dc.identifier.staffune-id:eghoshen
local.profile.orcid0000-0002-5203-4638en
local.identifier.unepublicationidune:1959.11/55246en
local.title.maintitleRepublican Liberty and Constitutional Constraintsen
local.output.categorydescriptionC1 Refereed Article in a Scholarly Journalen
local.uneassociationNoen
local.atsiresearchNoen
local.sensitive.culturalNoen
local.year.published2000en
local.fileurl.closedpublishedhttps://rune.une.edu.au/web/retrieve/627f2bc3-dada-4f94-bb21-fdade4553efcen
local.subject.for2020480410 Legal theory, jurisprudence and legal interpretationen
local.subject.seo2020230406 Legal processesen
Appears in Collections:Journal Article
School of Law
Files in This Item:
1 files
File SizeFormat 
Show simple item record

Page view(s)

252
checked on Nov 12, 2023

Download(s)

12
checked on Nov 12, 2023
Google Media

Google ScholarTM

Check


Items in Research UNE are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise indicated.